The Tripartite Synapse: An Elementary Reflection Mechanism

 

by Prof. Bernhard J. Mitterauer, M.D.

Institute of Forensic Neuropsychiatry and Gotthard Günther Archives

University of Salzburg, Salzburg, Austria

 

 

Abstract

 

Initially a tripartite synapse is described which embodies a synaptic model of glial-neuronal interaction. It consists of the presynaptic and postsynaptic components, a synaptic cleft and the glial component (astrocyte) which controls neurotransmission. Based on a biocybernetic model of a tripartite synapse, the glial-neuronal interaction can be interpreted as an elementary reflection mechanism. This reflection mechanism is essentially based on the principles of two-places-mirroring, intention, feasibility, negative feedback and rejection. Furthermore, it could embody standpoints of self-observation in the synaptic microdomain. Although the cooperation of these standpoints of self-observation in an undisturbed self-conscious brain seems mysterious and difficult to research, the paper offers a new proposal as to how and where elementary reflection mechanisms could be localized in the human brain.

 

 

Key words: tripartite synapse – glial-neuronal interaction – biocybernetic model – reflection      mechanism – standpoints of self-observation

 

 

 

1. INTRODUCTION

 

Presently, almost all brain oriented theories of consciousness are based solely on interpretations of the neuronal system of the brain, not referring to the glial system (for reviews see Black et al, 1998; Searle, 2004; Bennett & Hacker, 2004). In contrast to such exclusively neuronal approaches to consciousness, I have already proposed in several studies that the glial system in its interaction with the neuronal system could play a significant role in the processes underlying consciousness (Mitterauer, 1998, 2000b). Since glial-neuronal interactions have been experimentally well founded (Kettenmann & Ransom, 1995; Sykova et al, 1998; Haydon, 2001; Rouach et al, 2004), any comprehensive brain model or theory should take both systems of brain tissue into consideration.

     This paper focuses on glial-neuronal interactions in synapses, called tripartite synapses (Volterra et al, 2002; Auld & Robitaille, 2003). After the description of a tripartite synapse according to the model of Smit and coworkers (2001), a biocybernetic interpretation of this model as an elementary reflection mechanism is proposed.

     Supposing that tripartite synapses embody an elementary reflection mechanism, they could function as standpoints of self-observation. Since tripartite synapses of various transmitter types occur abundantly in the brain, it is a mystery how they cooperate in generating self-consciusness on the highest level of reflection. However, my proposal to localize elementary reflection mechanisms into tripartite synapses could be a first step towards a localization of consciousness processes in the synaptic microdomain of the brain. In considering the principles on which the reflection mechanism is based, this paper offers at least some new proposals for consciousness research in the neurosciences.

 

2. Tripartite Synapses

According to the prevailing view, chemical synaptic transmission exclusively involves bipartite synapses consisting of presynaptic and popstsynaptic components and a synaptic cleft, in which a presynaptically released neurotransmitter binds to cognate receptors in the postsynaptic cell. However, there is a new wave of information suggesting that glia, especially astrocytes, are intimately involved in the active control of neuronal activity and synaptic transmission.

     Meanwhile, experimental results are inspiring a major re-examination of the role of glia in the regulation of neural integration in the central nervous system (Kettenmann & Ransom, 1995; Bezzi & Volterra, 2001; Haydon, 2001; Auld & Robitaille, 2003). Glial cells (particularly astrocytes with their processes that contact or even enfold a synapse) modulate the “efficacy of synaptic transmission” (Mitterauer et al, 1996; Mitterauer, 1998, 2000a, 2000b,  2001a,  2001b; Oliet et al, 2001; Fields & Stevens-Graham, 2002; Mitterauer, 2003; Mitterauer & Kopp, 2003). Signals between astrocytes and neurons can be mediated by glutamate (Gallo & Ghiani, 2001), acetylcholine (Smit et al, 2001), and other neurotransmitters (Kimelberg et al, 1998), but also by intracellular calcium oscillations in astrocytes that have been hypothesized to affect synaptic cleft calcium concentrations (Cooper, 1995; Newman & Zahs, 1997) and, subsequently, the amount of neurotransmitter released from presynaptic terminals. In addition to modulating synaptic transmission in neuronal cells,  astrocytes may play a direct role in generating pacemaker rhythms (Mitterauer et al, 2000; Parri et al, 2001).

     More than a decade ago, Teichberg (1991) suggested that glial kainate receptors play a role in regulating synaptic efficacy and plasticity. Based on pertinent experimental findings, she proposed a synaptic model composed of three mutually interacting compartments: the presynaptic terminal, the postsynaptic membrane, and the glia, the latter possibly carrying some of the machinery regulating synaptic efficacy and plasticity. Until now, there is accumulating evidence that synaptically associated astrocytes (and perisynaptic Schwann cells) should be viewed as integral modulatory elements of tripartite synapses (Araque et al, 1999; Volterra et al, 2002).

 

3. Model of a Cholinergic Tripartite Synapse

Smit and coworkers (2001) proposed a model of a cholinergic tripartite synapse that might turn out to be a milestone for our understanding of the glial-neuronal interaction. But first let me shortly describe this type of tripartite synapse (Fig. 1). These authors identified a glia-derived soluble acetylcholine-binding protein (AChBP), which is a naturally occurring analogue of the ligand-binding domains of the nicotinic acetylcholine receptors (nAChRs). Like the nAChRs, it assembles into a heptamer with ligand-binding characteristics typical of a nicotinic receptor. Presynaptic releases of acetylcholine induce the secretion of AChBP through the glial secretory pathway, and once in the synaptic cleft, it acts as a molecular decoy, binding the transmitter and reducing its availability at the synapse.

     This model, which focuses on the role of AChBP in neurotransmission, suggests that there is a basal level of AChBP in the synaptic cleft, maintained by continuous release from the synaptic glial cells. Under conditions of active presynaptic transmitter release, high millimolar concentrations of free ACh will probably activate both postsynaptic receptors and nAChRs on the synaptic glial cells, which would enhance the release of AChBP, thus increasing its concentration in the synaptic cleft. This may either diminish or terminate the ongoing ACh response or raise the concentration of basal AChBP to the extent that subsequent responses to ACh are decreased.

    

4. Biocybernetic Model of a Tripartite Synapse

 

A simple biocybernetic model of a tripartite synapse could be helpful for interpreting an elementary reflection mechanism. Generally, a living system like man is endowed with intentional programs (hunger, desires, etc.) that strive for realization in the environment (Iberall & McCulloch, 1969). This intentional relationship of a living system with its environment can be described as an elementary behavioral cycle (Mitterauer, 2000a). Information from the environment actualizes an intentional program. If a living system is able to find appropriate objects for realizing a specific intentional program in the environment, then the cycle is closed, comparable to an experience. A negative feedback mechanism breaks off the information processing (Fig. 2).

     Such elementary behavioral cycles may also control the information processing in tripartite synapses. The production of neurotransmitters in the presynapse can be interpreted as “environmental information” stimulating the expression of BP in an astrocyte. BP may embody an “intentional program” that is ready for occupancy by an appropriate neurotransmitter. If an appropriate occupancy occurs (“realization of an intentional program”), the glial system negatively feeds back this “experience” to the presynapse. In parallel, this synaptic experience is transmitted to other cells in the glial-neuronal networks by occupancy of postsynaptic receptors (“information transmission”). Now, the cycle can start again (Fig. 3).

     But what makes astrocytes so intentional? In a series of papers, I have hypothesized that the glial system has a spatio-temporal boundary-setting function in its interaction with the neuronal system (Mitterauer et al, 1996; Mitterauer, 1998, 2000a, 2000b, 2001a, 2001b, 2003; Mitterauer & Kopp, 2003). With respect to a tripartite synapse, this would mean that astrocytes control synaptic information processing by setting temporal boundaries dependent on the occupancy of BP. In that case, glial BP embodies an essential parameter of synaptic information processing.

 

5. Elementary Reflection Mechanism in Tripartite Synapses

 

Instead of attacking the difficult problem of consciousness or even self-consciousness directly, my interpretation of a tripartite synapse is based on the more basic concept of reflection. Formally speaking, reflection is an act of recursion. In the basic case of recursion, the result of an act of computation becomes the object (argument) of the same act of computation (algorithm); thus switching between the outcome of an act and the object of the same act. Therefore, recursion is nothing more than the formal description of technical or biological processes based on feedback mechanisms. Feedback mechanisms in biological brains are abundant and experimentally well established (Damasio, 1992; Crick & Koch, 1995; Singer, 1995). If one assumes that feedback mechanisms already carry out the principle of reflection on this basic level, we must conform to Crick and Koch that feedback mechanisms generating the synchronization of neurons in the cerebral cortex represent elementary consciousness processes. These are not, however, self-conscious. But what kind of role do feedback mechanisms play on the synaptic level, especially in tripartite synapses? Could it be that the double structure of the brain in the sense of both neuronal and glial cells represents the ontological prerequisite for conscious  processes?

     Let me start out with a description of reflection based on a two-places-value system. According to Guenther (1966), the method of reflection which the human or any brain necessary uses, is a clear indication of the fact that the brain uses a place-value-system. Because in order to be reflected a concept has to turn up in the brain at least twice: once in the place where it originates and, second, in the place where its “mirror image” is reflected. Without this capacity no brain is capable of conscious awareness of anything. If we think of the world as a system of reality and thought, we actually think the very concept twice: as bona fide object and as reflection of the same. In order to keep both apart, the brain has to “locate” the identical concept in two different “places” in its pattern of awareness. My hypothesis is that Guenther’s conception of reflection can be easily transferred to the biocybernetic model of a tripartite synapse as proposed.

According to my interpretation a tripartite synapse is constituted of the following four principles: first, it consists of the neuronal and the glial system and, thus, can be interpreted as a two-places-system. Second, the neuronal synaptic system transmits information from other systems of the inner and outer environment embodied by neurotransmitters. In parallel it activates the glial system (astrocyte) via occupancy of the cognate glial receptors. Third, the glial system determines the neuronal information processing by its intentional programs embodied as glial binding proteins. Fourth, the glial system is setting temporal boundaries by breaking off information processing in the sense of a negative feedback. In other words: if the intentional programs are realized or feasible, further environmental information is temporarily rejected.

     Returning again to the method of reflection according to Guenther (1966), a tripartite synapse embodies an elementary reflection mechanism. Figure 4 shows a schematic diagram of that mechanism. There are two “places”, i.e. place x embodying the neuronal system and place y embodying the glial system. The basic concepts of the two places are the following: the environmental information processing representing “bona fide objects” occurs in the neuronal system. The glial system generates intentional programs in the sense of “thoughts” activated from the neuronal information. Since the concepts of the neuronal and glial systems are spatially separated, a mirroring is possible, supposing that the “thoughts” correspond to the “bona fide objects” in the environment. Such a synaptic architecture allows for an active reflection of a mirror situation via a negative feedback mechanism. In cybernetic terminology, feedback could embody purpose (Waldrop, 2001).

     Searle (2004) seems to be right when he mentions that the problem of intentionality is something of a mirror image of the problem of consciousness. According to the elementary reflection mechanism proposed, intentionality may play a decisive role in tripartite synapses, because a mirroring of concepts in a two-places-system needs an active decision process based on an intentional program. Intentional programs or thoughts are striving for realization (feasibility) in an appropriate environment. This may occur within tripartite synapses via occupancy of glial binding proteins with their cognate neurotransmitter embodying appropriate environmental objects (“bona fide objects”), similar to perception which is also action-oriented or intentional (Prinz, 1990), since a big amount of information must be rejected in order to recognize intended objects, subjects or situations. The same may occur in tripartite synapses. As soon as the negative feedback mechanism works, the synaptic information transmission is turned off, so that the environmental information is temporarily rejected.

 
6. Tripartite Synapses as Standpoints of Self-Observation

 

Generally speaking, the prefix “Self” points out that a system is capable of formal recursion or mechanic feedback. On higher levels as in the human brain, terms like self-observation or even self-consciousness are based on the ability of reflective thinking. Following my considerations so far, a tripartite synapse can be interpreted as an elementary standpoint of self-observation in the brain. I have already postulated that self-reflection may be represented in a manifold manner in the brain (Mitterauer, 1998), similar to the “Many Cartesian Theaters” (Damasio, 1992) or “many self-systems” (Baars, 1996). Here I am attempting to describe a basic synaptic reflection mechanism that could be underlying all higher level consciousness processes.

     One might argue that the neuronal system is also compartmentalized per se (Rall, 1995; Mel & Schiller, 2004). Furthermore, it is imaginable to see a many-place-system in the neuronal compartments as such. But according to my view there is a qualitative difference between the purely neuronal compartments and the glia determined compartments (Mitterauer, 2003; Mitterauer & Kopp, 2003). Neuronal compartments are merely functional for information processing, whereas glial-neuronal compartments may in addition have an information structuring potency based on the glial spatio-temporal boundary setting function (Mitterauer, 1998, 2000b, 2003, 2004a). Taking the tripartite synapse as a model system of glial-neuronal interaction in the sense of an elementary reflection mechanism, the glial system (astrocyte) may contribute two basic principles that could give rise to pure feedback mechanisms in the sense of reflection mechanisms. One of these principles is intention, the other rejection,  as already described.

     Supposing that tripartite synapses embody “micro-self-systems” which do not reach self-consciousness, we are confronted with the mystery how self-consciousness arises in the brain. This mystery is difficult to research. Current neuro-philosophical approaches which exclusively concern the neuronal system try to localize self-systems in various brain areas. From an anatomic-functional point of view, Baars (1996) provides numerous examples (e.g. split-brain patients, sensorimotor homunculus) which show that different self-systems can be represented in the brain. Damasio (1994) refers to a “neuronal Self”. Edelman (1992) also states his opinion that there is a biological self which he confines to subcortical homeostatic systems. Although we know that certain areas of the brain have priority for special tasks, it has not been possible to find a topological allocation for the different and complex reflection processes or to localize self-systems.

     My proposal to localize elementary reflection mechanisms into tripartite synapses could be a first step towards a localization of consciousness producing processes in the synaptic microdomain of the brain. But considering the different types of synapses that codetermine our behavior via specific proteins (neurotransmitter, glial binding proteins, etc.), and, in addition, the astronomic number (1014 to 1015) of synapses in the brain, we are challenged with a combinatorial explosion in computing possible interactions between the various types of tripartite synapses. Most importantly, we have no formal definition of the concept of Self available. An operational formulation could be: the Self is a living system capable of self-observation (Mitterauer & Pritz, 1978).

     We should, however, be able to find the part of the brain that integrates all of the different elmentary reflection mechanisms or subsystems of the Self in the undisturbed self-consciousness. Several decades ago, the group working with McCulloch considered the reticular formation in the brain stem as an “integrative matrix” (Scheibel & Scheibel, 1968) as well as a “central command system” (Kilmer, McCulloch, & Blum, 1969). Lately, Newman (1997) has suggested an “extended reticular-thalamic activating system” as a neural correlate for a “central conscious system” (see also Steriade, 1996). According to Churchland (2002), the most basic level of inner coordination and regulation occurs in the brain stem, anchoring what Damasio (1999) refers to as “the protoself”.

 
7. Future Prospects
 
Admittedly, the model of a tripartite synapse and its interpretation as an elementary reflection mechanism is hypothetical. First of all, the glial binding proteins must be identified in human brains. Presently we try to formalize a tripartite synapse interpreted as an intentional multiagent system (Mitterauer & Pfalzgraf, 2005). Such a robotic approach is promising, since the testing of my model with neurophysiological methods might be impossible. Perhaps neuroimaging could shed some light into the reflection mechanisms of tripartite synapses. However, if we succeed to build such a model in a robot brain, then it could teach us if we have a real biomimetic system.
     In his book “the mind doesn’t work that way”, Fodor (2000) speaks of “cognitive-neuro-science-fiction; there aren’t any proposals”. Despite that harsh criticism, Fodor is right that there is something like a stalemate in biologically based consciousness research. The present paper represents a further modest attempt to refer to the whole brain tissue in the sense of an interacting glia-neuronal double structure. To my knowledge this is the first synaptic model which describes an elementary reflection mechanism. It is based on principles like two-places-mirroring, intention, feasibility, negative feedback and rejection. Is there perhaps one or other proposal Fodor could be looking for?
 

 

REFERENCES

 

Bennett, M.R., & Hacker, P.M. (2004). Philosophical foundations of neuroscience. Malden:

      Blackwell Publishing.

 

Bezzi, P., & Volterra, A. (2001). A neuron-glia signalling network in the active brain. Current

      Opinions in Neurobiology, 11, 387-94.

 

Block, N., Flanagan, O., & Güzeldere, G. (Eds.) (1998). The nature of consciousness:

     philosophical  debates. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

 

Churchland, P.S. (2002). Self-representation in nervous systems. Science, 296, 308-310.

 

Cooper, M.S. (1995). Intercellular signalling in neuronal-glial networks. BioSystems, 34, 65-

      85.

 

Crick, F., & Koch, C. (1995). Are we aware of neural activity in primary visual cortex?

     Nature, 375, 121-123.

 

Damasio, A.R. (1992). The selfless consciousness. Behavioral Brain Sciences, 15, 208-209.

 

Damasio, A.R. (1994). Descartes’ Error. Emotion, Reason and the Human Brain. Putnam’s

      Son, New York.

 

 Damasio, A.R. (1999). The feeling of what happens. New York: Harcourt.

 

Edelman, G. (1992). Bright Air, Brilliant Fire: On the Matter of the Mind. Basic Books, New

     York.

 

Fields, R.D., & Stevens-Graham, B. (2002). New insights into neuron-glia communication.

     Science, 298, 556-62.

 

Fodor, J. (2000). the mind doesn’t work that way. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

 

Gallo, V., & Ghiani, C.A. (2001). Glutamate receptors in glia: New cells, new inputs and new

     functions. Trends in Pharmacological Sciences, 21, 252-258.

 

Guenther, G. (1966). Some remarks on many-valued logic. In L.J. Fogel, On the design of

     conscious automata (pp. 89-95). Clearinghouse: Federal scientific and technical

     information.

 

Haydon, P.Q. (2001). Glia: Listening and talking to the synapse. Nature Reviews.

     Neuroscience, 2, 185-193.

 

Iberall, A.S., & McCulloch, W.S. (1969). The organizing principle of complex living systems.

     Transactions of the ASME, 6, 290-294.

 

Kettenmann, H., & Ransom, B.R. (Eds.) (1995). Neuroglia. New York: Oxford University

     Press.

 

Kilmer, W.L., McCulloch, W.S., & Blum, J. (1969). A model of the vertebrate central

     command system. International Journal of Man-Machine Studies, 1, 279-309.

 

Kimelberg, H.K., Jalonen, T.O., Aoki, C., & McCarthy, K. (1998). Transmitter receptor and

      uptake systems in astrocytes and their relation to behaviour. In P.R. Laming, E. Sykova,

      A. Reichenbach, G.I. Hatton, & H. Bauer (Eds.), Glial cells: Their role in behaviour (pp.

     107-129). Cambridge: University Press.

 

Mel, B.W., & Schiller, J. (2004). On the fight between excitation and inhibition: location is

     everything. Science, 250, 1-3.

 

Mitterauer, B. (1998). An interdisciplinary approach towards a theory of consciousness.

     BioSystems, 45, 99-121.

 

Mitterauer, B. (2000a). Clock genes, feedback loops and their possible role in the etiology of

     bipolar disorders: an integrative model. Medical Hypotheses, 55, 155-159.

 

Mitterauer, B. (2000b). Some principles for conscious robots. Journal of Intelligent Systems,

     10, 27-56.

 

Mitterauer, B. (2001a). Clocked perception system. Journal of Intelligent Systems, 11,

     269-297.

 

Mitterauer, B. (2001b). The loss of ego boundaries in schizophrenia: a neuromolecular

     hypothesis. Medical Hypotheses, 56, 614-621.

 

Mitterauer, B.J. (2003). The loss of self-boundaries: towards a neuromolecular theory of

     schizophrenia. BioSystems, 72, 209-215.

 

Mitterauer, B.J. (2004a). Imbalance of glial-neuronal interaction in synapses: a possible

     mechanism of the pathophysiology of bipolar disorder. The Neuroscientist, 10, 199-206.

 

Mitterauer, B.J. (2004b). Verlust der Selbst-Grenzen: Entwurf einer interdisziplinären

     Theorie der Schizophrenie. Wien: Springer-Verlag.

 

Mitterauer, B., & Pritz, W.F. (1978). The concept of the Self: a theory of self-observation.

     International Review of Psycho-Analysis, 5, 179-188.

 

Mitterauer, B., Leitgeb, H., & Reitboeck, H. (1996). The neuro-glial synchronization

     hypothesis. Recent Research Development in Biological Cybernetics, 1, 137-155.

 

Mitterauer, B., Garvin, A.M., & Dirnhofer, R. (2000). The sudden infant death syndrome

     (SIDS): A neuro-molecular hypothesis. The Neuroscientist, 6, 154-158.

 

Mitterauer, B.J., & Kopp, C. (2003). The self-composing brain: towards a glial-neuronal brain

     theory. Brain and Cognition, 51, 357-367.

 

Mitterauer, B.J., & Pfalzgraf, J. (2005). Towards a biomathematical model of intentional

     autonomous multiagent systems. (In preparation).

 

Newman, J. (1997). Putting the puzzle together, Part I: towards a general theory of the neural

     correlates of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 4, 47-66.

 

Newman, E.A., & Zahs, K.R. (1997). Calcium waves in retinal glial cells. Science, 275,

     844-846.

 

Oliet, S.H., Piet, R., & Poulain, D.A. (2001). Control of glutamate clearance and synaptic

     efficacy by glial coverage of neurons. Science, 292, 923-926.

 

Parri, H.R., Gould, T.M., & Crunelli, V. (2001). Spontaneous astrocytic Ca2+ oscillations in

     situ drive NMDAR-mediated neuronal excitation. Nature Neuroscience, 4, 803-812.

 

Prinz, W. (1990). A common coding approach to perception and action. In O. Neumann & W.

     Prinz (Eds.), Relationships between perception and action (pp. 167-201). Berlin: Springer

     Verlag.

 

Rall, W. (1995). Theoretical significance of dendritic trees for neuronal input-output relations.

     In I. Segev, J. Rinzel, & G.M. Shepherd (Eds.), The theoretical foundation of dendritic

     function (pp. 122-146). Cambridge: The MIT Press.

 

Rouach, N., Koulakoff, A., & Giaume, C. (2004). Neurons set the tone of gap junctional

     communication in astrocytic networks. Neurochemistry International, 45, 265-272.

 

Scheibel, M.E., & Scheibel, A.B. (1968). The brain stem core: An integrative matrix. In M.

     Mesarovic (Ed.), Systems theory and biology (pp. 261-285). New York: Springer Verlag.

 

Searle, J.R. (2004). Mind: a brief introduction. Oxford: University Press.

 

Singer, W. (1995). Synchronization of neuronal responses as a putative binding mechanism.

      In M.A. Arbib (Ed.), The Handbook of Brain Theory and Neural Networks.

      MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

 

Smit, A.B., Syed, N.I., & Schaap, D., et al (2001). A glial-derived acetylcholine-binding

     protein that modulates synaptic transmission. Nature, 411, 261-268.

 

Steriade, D.A. (1996). Arousal: Revisiting the reticular activating system. Science, 272,

      225-226.

 

Sykova, E., Hansson, E., Roenbaeck, L., & Nicholson, C. (1998). Glial regulation of the

     neuronal microenvironment. In P.R. Laming, E. Sykova, A. Reichenbach, G.I. Hatton, &

     H. Bauer (Eds.), Glial cells: Their role in behaviour (pp. 130-163).

     Cambridge: University Press.

 

Teichberg, V.I. (1991). Glial glutamate receptors: Likely actors in brain signalling.

     Official Publication of the Federation of American Societies for Experimental Biology, 5,

     3086-3091.

 

Volterra, A., Magistretti, P., Haydon, P. (2002). The tripartite synapse – glia in synaptic

     transmission.  Oxford (UK): Oxford University Press.

 

Waldrop, M.M. (2001). The dream machine. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books.

 

Figure 1.  Model of the role of AChBP in neurotransmission

 

A basal level of AChBP is present in the synaptic cleft. Presynaptic ACh release can lead to activation of postsynaptic receptors and to EPSPs. In parallel, nAChRs on glia are activated, causing increased release of AChBP into the synapse, which leads to suppression of cholinergic transmission (reproduced from Nature, Vol. 411, May 2001, pp. 261-268, Fig. 8, with permission of first author A.B. Smit and Nature Publishing Group).

 


Figure 2.  Elementary behavioral cycle

 

An information from the environment activates one or more intentional programs. If a living system is able to find appropriate objects for realizing a specific intentional program in the environment, then the cycle is closed (—│), comparable to an experience (Mitterauer, 2004a).


Figure 3.  Biocybernetic model of a tripartite synapse

 

The production of neurotransmitter (NT) in the presynapse provides the system with “environmental information” stimulating the expression of glial binding protein (glBP) in an astrocyte. GlBP may embody “intentional programs” realized by appropriate neurotransmitter occupancy. If an appropriate occupancy occurs, the glial system negatively feedbacks (—│) this “experience” to the presynapse. In parallel, this synaptic experience is transmitted to other systems by occupancy of postsynaptic receptors (Mitterauer, 2004a).

 


Figure 4.  Schematic diagram of an elementary reflection mechanism in

                  tripartite synapses.

 

Place x (red) represents the neuronal component, place y (green) the glial component of a tripartite synapse. After activation (arrow) of the glial system by the neuronal system, the intentional programs (“thoughts”) are mirrored (double arrow) to the environmental information (“bona fide objects”). A negative feedback determines that the mirroring breaks off (fat bar) the information processing (“embodiment of purpose”), which corresponds to an elementary  reflection mechanism.

[ back to "Publications & Special Reports" ]
[ BWW Society Home Page ]